Thursday, December 28, 2006

LEGO Difference Machine

LEGO Difference Machine
Check out the LEGO Difference Machine here.

Sunday, December 10, 2006

Math + JavaScript = Cool

Check out ASCIIMathML and ASCIIsvg to learn how to display math equations and graphs in your website using nothing but JavaScript. You've probably seen ASCIIMathML in action in some of my other posts.

Saturday, December 02, 2006

Golomb Ruler

In mathematics, the term "Golomb Ruler" refers to a set of non-negative integers such that no two distinct pairs of numbers from the set have the same difference. Conceptually, this is similar to a ruler constructed in such a way that no two pairs of marks measure the same distance. An Optimal Golomb Ruler (OGR) is the shortest Golomb Ruler possible for a given number of marks. However, finding (and proving) OGR's becomes exponentially more difficult as the number of marks increases, and it is for this reason that we have turned to the web for help in finding the OGR's with 24 and more marks.

For more information, check out the distributed.net: Project OGR page and more info at MathWorld and Wikipedia.

Thursday, November 30, 2006

Antikythera Mechanism

The Antikythera mechanism is an ancient mechanical analog computer (as opposed to digital computer) designed to calculate astronomical positions. It was discovered in the Antikythera wreck off the Greek island of Antikythera, between Kythera and Crete, and has been dated to about 150-100 BC. Click here for more information.

Sunday, November 05, 2006

InstaCalc Online Calculator

InstaCalc is a vision for a fast, simple and powerful calculator. You can embed it in your website or blog.

Wednesday, November 01, 2006

The Curta Calculator

Curta II Calculator
Here are some links about the Curta calculator. Nice little machine.

Wednesday, September 13, 2006

44th Known Mersenne Prime Found!

Less than a year after their last discovery, the Central Missouri State University (CMSU) team, led by professors Curtis Cooper and Steven Boone, has broken their own record for the largest known prime number: 232,582,657-1.

Tuesday, August 22, 2006

Great Mathematical Books

  • Journey Through Genius, by William Dunham © 1990.

  • The Mathematical Universe, by William Dunham © 1994.

  • Proofs Without Words II, by Roger B. Nelsen © 2000.

  • Proofs Without Words, by Roger B. Nelsen © 1993.

  • Fermat's Last Theorem, by Simon Singh © 1997.

  • The Universal Book of Mathematics: From Abracadabra to Zeno's Paradoxes, by David Darling © 2004.

  • The Mathematics of Ciphers: Number Theory and RSA Cryptography, by S. C. Coutinho © 1998.

  • Axiomatic Set Theory, by Patrick Suppes © 1972.

  • Abel's Proof, by Peter Pesic © 2003.

  • Hilbert's Tenth Problem, by Yuri V. Matiyasevich © 1996.

  • Prime Numbers, by David Wells © 2005.
  • Sunday, July 09, 2006

    The Mathematics Genealogy Project

    The intent of this project is to compile information about ALL the mathematicians of the world. We earnestly solicit information from all schools who participate in the development of research level mathematics and from all individuals who may know desired information.

    Please notice: Throughout this project when we use the word "mathematics" or "mathematician" we mean that word in a very inclusive sense. Thus, all relevant data from statistics, or computer science or operations research is welcome.

    In the following paragraphs we shall try to outline our goals and our underlying philosophy for the GENEALOGY PROJECT. It is our goal to list all individuals who have received a doctorate in mathematics. For each individual we plan to show the following:

    • The complete name of the degree recipient.

    • The name of the university which awarded the degree.

    • The year in which the degree was awarded.

    • The complete title of the dissertation.

    • The complete name(s) of the advisor(s).

    Hilbert's 23 Problems (#10)

    Definition: Given a Diophantine equation with any number of unknown quantities and with rational integral numerical coefficients: To devise a process according to which it can be determined by a finite number of operations whether the equation is solvable in rational integers.

    What this basically says is that is there a way for us to give a boolean answer to whether any such equation is solvable or not without necessarily knowing the solution?

    The answer turns out to be no. Get the book Hilbert's Tenth Problem by Yuri V. Matiyasevich to understand why.

    Although I've started reading this book, I must say that it is a little above my level of understanding. I've already read the first chapter twice just to get some basic understanding of his definitions. However, the commentary at the end of Chapter 3 was absolutely remarkable.

    In my number theory and abstract algebra classes in college (university doesn't have that nice ring to it), we learned that there does not exist any polynomial that returns only primes for all integer arguments, but rather only for some (Euler's $f(x) = x^2 + x + 41$).

    Julia Robinson proved in 1952 that the binomial coefficients and the factorial are exponential Diophantine, and gave an exponential Diophantine representation for the set of all prime numbers. In 1960, Putnam noted that a Diophantine set is the positive part of the range of a polynomial. Thus, it became clear (to someone) that if exponentiation were established to be Diophantine, it would become possible to construct a polynomial such that the positive values it assumed would coincide precisely with the prime numbers. In 1971a, Matiyasevich gave the first upper bound of 24 variables in his Russian article, which was later reduced to 21 in the appendix of the English translation.

    In 1976, Jones, Sato, Wada and Wiens exhibited the following polynomial:

    $(k + 2){1 - [wz + h + j - q]^2 - [(gk + 2g + k + 1)(h + j) + h - z]^2$ - $[2n + p + q + z - e]^2$ - $[16(k + 1)^3(k + 2)(n + 1)^2 + 1 - f^2]^2$ - $[e^3(e + 2)(a + 1)^2 + 1 - o^2]^2$ - $[(a^2 - 1)y^2 + 1 - x^2]^2$ - $[n + l + v - y]^2$ - $[((a + u^2(u^2 - a))^2 - 1)(n + 4dy)^2 + 1 - (x + cu)^2]^2$ - $[(a^2 - 1)t^2 + 1 - m^2]^2$ - $[q + y(a - p -1) + s(2ap + 2a - p^2 - 2p - 2) - x]^2$ - $[z + pl(a - p) + t(2ap - p^2 - 1) - p\m]^2$ - $[ai + k + 1 - l -i]^2$ - $[p + l(a - n - 1) + b(2an +2a - n^2 - 2n - 2) - m]^2\}$

    This polynomial contains 26 variables (all the letters of the English alphabet), and the set of its positive values is exactly the set of all prime numbers. Note: The polynomial written above, representing only primes, is itself the product of two polynomials.

    Later, the bound was further reduced to 12 variables by Wada in 1975, and by Jones, Sato, Wada and Wiens in 1976. Currently, the record is at 10 variables, achieved by Matiyasevich in 1977a.

    Sunday, June 11, 2006

    Mathematical Poetry

    Finite Simple Group (of order two)


    A Klein Four original by Matt Salomone

    URL: The Klein Four Group
    Movie: Finite Simple Group (of Order Two)

    The path of love is never smooth
    But mine's continuous for you
    You're the upper bound in the chains of my heart
    You're my Axiom of Choice, you know it's true

    But lately our relation's not so well-defined
    And I just can't function without you
    I'll prove my proposition and I'm sure you'll find
    We're a finite simple group of order two

    I'm losing my identity
    I'm getting tensor every day
    And without loss of generality
    I will assume that you feel the same way

    Since every time I see you, you just quotient out
    The faithful image that I map into
    But when we're one-to-one you'll see what I'm about
    'Cause we're a finite simple group of order two

    Our equivalence was stable,
    A principal love bundle sitting deep inside
    But then you drove a wedge between our two-forms
    Now everything is so complexified

    When we first met, we simply connected
    My heart was open but too dense
    Our system was already directed
    To have a finite limit, in some sense

    I'm living in the kernel of a rank-one map
    From my domain, its image looks so blue,
    'Cause all I see are zeros, it's a cruel trap
    But we're a finite simple group of order two

    I'm not the smoothest operator in my class,
    But we're a mirror pair, me and you,
    So let's apply forgetful functors to the past
    And be a finite simple group, a finite simple group,
    Let's be a finite simple group of order two
    (Oughter: "Why not three?")

    I've proved my proposition now, as you can see,
    So let's both be associative and free
    And by corollary, this shows you and I to be
    Purely inseparable. Q. E. D.

    My Poem


    by Eve Andersson

    There once was a number named pi
    Who frequently liked to get high.
    All he did every day
    Was sit in his room and play
    With his imaginary friend named i.

    There once was a number named e
    Who took way too much LSD.
    She thought she was great.
    But that fact we must debate;
    We know she wasn't greater than 3.

    There once was a log named Lynn
    Whose life was devoted to sin.
    She came from a tree
    Whose base was shaped like an e.
    She's the most natural log I've seen.

    eve

    A Young Don From Trinity


    There was a young Don from Trinity
    Who solved the square root of infinity
    While counting the digits
    He was seized by the fidgets
    Dropped science and took up divinity

    Anonymous.

    A New Solution to an Old Problem


    The Topologist's child was quite hyper
    'Til she wore a Moebius diaper.
    The mess on the inside
    Was thus on the outside
    And it was easy for someone to wipe her.

    By Eleanor Ninestein.

    An Analyst, Surname of Nero


    An analyst, surname of Nero,
    Is my mathematical hero.
    Says he, "When in doubt,
    I always start out,
    'Given $\epsilon$ > 0 ...'."

    By James R. Martino,
    Department of Mathematics
    The Johns Hopkins University
    Baltimore, MD 21218.

    Thursday, June 01, 2006

    Continuous, Nowhere Differentiable Functions

    The Weierstrass function $f_a(x) = sum_(k=1)^infty sin(pi k^a x)/{pi k^a}$ (originally defined for a = 2) is an example of a continuous function, but differentiable only on a set of points of measure zero.

    The function was published by Weierstrass but, according to lectures and writings by Kronecker and Weierstrass, Riemann seems to have claimed already in 1861 that the function f(x) is not differentiable on a set dense in the reals. However, Ullrich (1997) indicates that there is insufficient evidence to decide whether Riemann actually bothered to give a detailed proof for this claim. du Bois-Reymond (1875) stated without proof that every interval of f contains points at which f does not have a finite derivative, and Hardy (1916) proved that it does not have a finite derivative at any irrational and some of the rational points. Gerver (1970) and Smith (1972) subsequently proved that f has a finite derivative (namely, 1/2) at the set of points x = ${2A+1}/{2B+1}$ where A and B are integers. Gerver (1971) then proved that f is not differentiable at any point of the form ${2A}/{2B+1}$ or ${2A+1}/{2B}$. Together with the result of Hardy that f is not differentiable at any irrational value, this completely solved the problem of the differentiability of f.

    Since then, a number of mathematicians have developed examples of nowhere continuous, differentiable (CND) functions and it has been shown that these types of functions are the norm (PDF).

    One thing that should be obvious is that these functions are not lines in the geometric sense. These are all limits of other continuous functions, that are mostly differentiable, which converge to a nowhere differentiable function.

    In Euclidean geometry, a polygon (or straight line) should only be drawn by pencil and straighthedge. If we were to draw any line, then the straighthedge can be omitted and a person only needs to trace the pencil from the starting point to the finish using whatever path they like. Assuming that the person isn't drunk, the line should be of finite length since we are drawing a line fron start to finish. Thus, any line segment that is a subset of that line, must have an even smaller finite length.

    However, with CND functions, if you are to pick a point with a pencil and try to trace it to any other point, you will not go anywhere. The reason being is that the standard definition of a line is not met with the CND function. Since at any point, the function is not differentiable, the line would not know which direction to take. Thus, it would appear to vibrate like an electron held motionless in place.

    Therein lies the beauty of such functions. They exist and are continuous, but are not real in the geometric sense.